Often it is said that Robert Pippinโs Hegel is too Kantian or too Fichtean. By this is meant, not so much that it is wrong per se that Pippin emphasises the Kantian and Fichtean elements, but rather that something crucial is left out by his reading of Hegel. His is, supposedly, a deflationary reading of Hegel, a kind of bowdlerised version of Hegel the thoroughbred metaphysician in the Spinozan sense, say. Too much emphasis is put, by Pippin, on the fact that we canโt know Being without a dependence on the categories in virtue of which Being can first be determined in and through self-determining thought.1 Despite the fact that Pippin, certainly more recently, insists on a metaphysical reading, and points to the fact that it is Beingโs own intelligibility that is at issue, not just our subjective perspective on it,2 his Hegelian detractors have often taken and still take Pippinโs Hegel to be unappealingly unhegelian in some important sense. So in what sense is Pippinโs Hegel then not sufficiently โmetaphysicalโ or โontologicalโ, not enough of a Hegel, as Pippinโs critics believe?
Much can be said about this and I certainly donโt intend to be exhaustive here. But one passage that I reread last weekend in an interview with Stephen Houlgate from a few years ago in which he chooses as one of the important books in the secondary literature on Hegel Pippinโs much-lauded and widely cited monograph Hegelโs Idealism from 1989, is striking in that it illuminates, in a perfectly succinct manner, the difference between Pippinโs interpretation of Hegel (esp. in the Logic) and Houlgateโs own, which can be considered the most important position that is, in many ways, the contrary of the Pippinian approach.
Houlgate has published several pieces in which he criticises Pippin in some detail, and I believe he does so too in his latest tome on the Being Logic (which I havenโt read). Without delving into the specifics of his critique of Pippin elsewhere, which merits closer attentionโsomething I cannot pay hereโI want to look at this particular passage from the interview. It is of course merely a text fragment from an interview, not by any means a scholarly paper, but I think, having read Houlgateโs interpretations of Pippin over the years and having discussed this extensively in personal meetings in the past, the fragment is a good reflection of his current position on this matter. I think it makes it clear in what sense Pippin and Houlgate differ and why, I think, Houlgateโs position is ultimately untenable, not in the light of what Pippin believes, but more in general, as a reading of Hegel as a post-Kantian philosopher, which Houlgate himself acknowledges.
Houlgate captures one important element of Pippinโs reading of Hegel accurately:
What people donโt always recognise is that Kant is not simply saying that we need certain categories in order to make sense of the world; he is saying that intuitions themselves have to be understood in terms of certain categories in order to be objects for cognition. This is in the B deduction of the Critique of Pure Reason. So the categories are conditions not just of our experience of objects but of objects themselves as objects of cognition. Thatโs really important to Pippinโs Kant.
Indeed, this is the identity claim that lies at the heart of the B-Deduction, which Pippin takes to be the nub of the Hegelian point about the Absolute, or what in his early work, Hegel still called โabsolute identityโ. It is the original synthetic unity of apperception that constitutes the identity between Being and thought, between object and subject. This absolute identity should not be read as some kind of presupposed, original absolute substance which has particular attributes, one of which is thought or thought determinations that mirror or map onto its ontological attributes. Rather, absolute identity is a logical condition of cognition in virtue of which it can be seen, in thought, that and how the notions of โbeingโ and โthoughtโ itself basically derive from the function of unity that first establishes the identity between Being and thought, between the understanding and its object. It shows that in fact Being and thought are not absolute opposites sundered from each other in an absolute manner, as Houlgate himself points out in the interview in his answer to the question what absolute knowledge is.
This function of unity is Reason itself. It is not some substance, it is not Being as such, it is nothing pre- or non-rational or prior to thought. Reason itself is the Absolute. It is Reason that constitutes the identity of Being and thought, in that Being is as much subject to the conditions of thought as is thought itself. To put the point in Kantโs terms: the categories, which determine how objects for thought are constituted, are identical to the functions of thought, which dictate how thought works. Objects just are what the categories determine them to be.
Now this is where Houlgate notes a crucial difference. As much as it is true that thereโs no gap between how the categories determine our thought or experience of an object and how this object itself is an object for thought, there is something about the object that prevents it from being made identical to its being thought, something that is apparently not captured by the logic of thought if we take the Pippinian/Kantian route. And this has got to do not just with objects per se, but how we approach the Logic of Being as such, starting with the very first pages in the Logic, where any determinate object for thought is not yet an object of study. The categories that are discussed in the beginning of the Logic are more primitive and concern Being in a far more indeterminate sense. Pippinโs โapperceptiveโ approach that focuses on object determinacy seems to run ahead of the analysis in the Logic. To be โsomethingโ, let alone to be any object of a possible judgement, is not the most primordial sense of Being. As a category โsomethingโ appears only somewhat further on in the Being Logic, and judgement first appears in the last part of the Logic. Houlgate hints at this:
Pippin thinks that the first part of the Logicโthe logic of beingโconsiders the problems that arise when one attempts to understand what there is through simple categories, such as โsomethingโ. For him, Hegelโs exposure of the failure of this attempt then leads to the discovery, later in the Logic, of the further categories that are in fact required for something to be a determinate object of cognition. In my view, by contrast, the logic of being has a more positive role and simply unfolds what it is to be โsomethingโ, โfiniteโ and so on. (boldface added)
First, Houlgate appears to allude to a sense of Being not captured by the determinacy of thought, as if Being itself determines itself prior to or independently of thought doing so. It seems that, for Houlgate, we must be able to talk about Being itself apart from how Being appears as more determinate forms of Being in judgements. In Houlgateโs view, the โapperceptiveโ line of interpretation that Pippin espouses is derivative of, or secondary to, a more primordial sense in which Being is to be characterised. Pippin has labelled such a reading of the Logic โobjectivistโ. It is โobjectivistโ in two senses: this type of reading opposes a โsubjectivistโ construal such as Pippinโs apperception-centric approach, and it is suggested that an independent mind-independent account can be given of the categories of Being in the Being Logic, as if Being itself suggests the unfolding of these categories out of itself, which we merely need to register in the analysis. The Being Logic is then this chronicle, as it were, of the categories of Being.
Itโs just a sentence on which he does not elaborate in the interview, but the phrase with which Houlgate describes the Being Logic is telling, i.e. it โsimply unfolds what it is to be โsomethingโ, โfiniteโ and so onโ. Note Houlgateโs emphasis on โisโ, which suggests that the copula, in e.g. speculative judgements such as โBeing is Nothingโ, should be read as a real predicate, implying an ontological reading of predication, referring to an existential. By contrast, Pippin doesnโt read concepts such as โbeingโ, โnothingโ, โbecomingโ, โsomethingโ as properties of an independently and prior given Being, but as concepts that purport to be determinations of Being that in fact, taken as such, fail to be such things. That doesnโt mean they are meaningless or donโt have a distinct role in the dialectic of the Logic: on the contrary, they lead us, by way of a conceptual analysis which is a close analogue of Kantโs Deduction, to an increasingly determinate, substantial concept of Being. One should not take these concepts as if each of them somehow mirrors or expresses an actual aspect of Being, even right at the start of the analysis. To do so would imply that pure Being is given as such, independently of thought and prior to it, so that we only have to map out what its characteristics are. This would subvert the entire Hegelian premise that we start out from the standpoint of Reason that has superseded any distinction between a determinative understanding and its opposite, the โabsolutely existingโ world of objects.
Neither Being nor objects can be taken to be given, independently of and prior to the analysis of concepts that the Logic sets in motion. What we have at the start of the Logic is merely thought thinking its own minimal determinations, or as Pippin aptly puts it: โthinking thinking thinkingโ, i.e. thought thinking itself. To appeal to a notion as โsheer beingโ at this point, as Houlgate does, is not vindicated by the logical dialectic of Hegelโs text, and it in fact also contradicts his own motto of โpresuppositionlessnessโ as the characteristic of Hegelian logic.
Secondly, for Houlgate, it seems that the categories of thought determining what something is are ipso facto not sufficient for determining what something is. But here too he seems to smuggle in an ontological element that is supposedly not captured by the categorial determination itself. This suggests that he reintroduces a dualist constellation of the relation between thought and Being, whereby Being is absolutely independent of thought even though thought is capable of determining Being. I recall here Houlgateโs own mantra, often half-jokingly invoked during our many fruitful but vigorous debates, โthought is Being, and Being is thoughtโ. So he most certainly doesnโt intend to reintroduce a dualism between the two. But he does in fact appear to do so, it seems to me.
This is suggested by his use of the term โsheer beingโ and the claim that โbeing is not collapsibleโ into thought determining Being. This might sound plausible: for isnโt it intuitively right to say that Being has a structure of its own quite independently of how we determine it to be? Isnโt Being something objective that is not reducible to how we subjectively determine it? And mustnโt we distinguish between necessary conditions (the categories) and sufficient conditions of knowledge after all? Isnโt it true to say that something just is even apart from whether or not it is known by us or anyone?
In some sense, Houlgateโs instinctual sense that there is something independent about Being (and Iโm not sure Houlgate would be happy about my use of the term โindependentโ here), and therefore everything that is, might seem right. That I judge some object x to have a certain property or quality and that that object therefore is as such an object for my thought in that Iโm capable of making a judgement about it doesnโt in the least mean that the objectโs existence is constituted by my thought. My judgement or even multiple judgements donโt exhaust the objectโs being what it is. This is quite in line with Kantโs statement that the existence (Dasein) of an object is not constituted by the functions of thought. So the identity of object and thought doesnโt seem to go as far as the Being of the object is concerned. Hereโs where Kantโs thing in itself comes into play, which I shall not elaborate on here, as this is another tricky interpretative minefield about which entire monographs have been (and still are) written.
What is important to note here is that for Pippinโs Hegel thereโs no longer any Kantian reticence with respect to the ontological implications of the identity claim at the heart of the Deduction, and so the Logic: the absolute identity claim that Kant establishes in the B-Deduction is no longer linked to a restriction thesis, that is, there is no restriction of our possible knowledge to mere appearances. Instead, the identity claim concerns the intelligibility of Being itself. Obviously, this does not mean that we canโt make false judgements or that there isnโt some sort of independence of the objectโs existence, namely in an empirical sense (no German idealist in his right mind claims that tables are mere objects of the mind in the empirical sense). The identity claim is rather about the fact that there is no in principle gap between thought and Being. What thought determines there to be is all that there intelligibly can be.
It is precisely here that Pippin and Houlgate seem to diverge, though it strikes me as difficult to comprehend why Houlgate could not agree to this other than because of a tendency to objectify the terms in the analysis, precisely what Pippin considers to be an unwarranted โobjectivismโ. Or, Houlgateโs reserve here might stem from a quite familiar, and thus understandable, lingering reluctance to give up on the idea of Beingโs independence of thought, a conservative resistance to consistently subjectify ontology. It would appear that Pippin is more radically Hegelian here than Houlgate.
Paradoxically, Houlgate seems more Kantian in spirit here than Pippin: He doesnโt seem convinced that the identity claim really captures Being itself. โSheer beingโ is the term he uses. Kant would agree to an extent, in that the being of a thing in its complete determinacy, its in-itselfness, is not captured by the identity claim of the B-Deduction (though of course, its existence qua existence is determined by the category โexistenceโ). This is of course not how Houlgate sees it himself, as heโs, following Hegel, damning about Kantโs notion of the thing in itself.
That Houlgate diverges from the identity reading that Pippin espouses is made explicit by this passage:
[I]t seems to me that there is still something missing from the position adopted by Pippinโs own โmetaphysicalโ Hegel: for, in my view, there is an element of sheer being that is not collapsible into being for a knower or being an object of cognition. When we think about this table, we think that that table is there. Yes, it is known by us, but it also has a being and an identity of its own. My Hegel is thus trying to work out the categories that structure not only (a) how we must think of things; not only (b) what something must be to be an object of cognition; but also (c) what is to be at all. I think this third element is missing from Pippinโs account. For me, the long and the short of it is that Pippinโs Hegel ends up being a little too close to Fichte, for whom also โto beโ is โto be for a subjectโ. (boldface added)
The phrasing of โan element of sheer being that is not collapsible into being for a knowerโ is significant. It strikes me as however undermining the notion of absolute identity that is central to Hegelโs thought. Either there is an identity between thought and Being, or there isnโt. Of course, in any particular judgement about an object, I could be mistaken as to whether I do indeed see an object, or whether I correctly or not attribute this or that property to the object. But there is an in principle identity between my ability to cognise the object and the objectโs being. This is the Kantian element that Hegel, according to Pippin, takes over and modifies by taking out the stuff about pure intuition. And you canโt fall back behind it without jeopardising Hegelโs Kantian legacy: for itโs the central part of it. Houlgate does seem to fall back behind it: Being is not collapsible into being for thought, meaning that there is an unbridgeable gap between Being as such, sheer Being (whatever that may mean), and our grasp of it. Or so it seems.
For Hegel, properly speaking, and this is what Pippin emphasises, there could not be an intelligible distinction between (b) and (c). What could it be for something to be like that is not graspable in cognition in virtue of the categories? Or more charitablyโfor Houlgate might be taken to argue that everything about Being should in principle be graspable by thought, without however Being collapsing into its being grasped by thoughtโwhat exactly makes the difference for something to be in distinction from it being grasped by thought? This seems to point to a different set of determinations that express that difference. But how is that difference accounted for in view of the unity of thought and Being? In other words, how can what seems to have a being on its own, having โan identity of its ownโ, still be grasped by thought? Hegel is not a Kantian idealist, who can perfectly consistently juggle two different irreducible sets of rules governing separate realms; so for Hegel, any claim about different ostensibly irreducible ways of being, being for cognition and being on its own, must be accounted for in terms of a single, unitary set of categorial rules. If Being is in principle graspable by thoughtโand I think Houlgate would not dare deny thisโthen there must, in some specifiable manner, be an identity between Being for cognition and Being on its own.
So the question is, if there were a distinction between the categories structuring (b) and (c), are we talking about the same set of categories structuring both (b) and (c), or are there two different sets of categories that structure how objects are for us and their sheer being โat allโ respectively? And if there are two such different sets of categories, in what way are they both related to thought and its function of unity? In other words, how can thought grasp the transition between (c) and (b), or put differently, how and in virtue of what does thought combine the putative two sets of categories that govern (b) and (c) so that what we determinately grasp in thought is in fact how Being itself determinately is, that is, such that it is sheer Being in fact what we determine? It seems to me that Houlgateโs non-collapsibility thesis is in at least potential conflict with his commitment to the absolute identity thesis about thought and Being.
These logical conundrums can be avoided by adopting the identity reading that Pippin proposes. There simply is no intelligent way in which Being can be determined other than through the categories that constitute the ways in which Being is for thought. There just is no sheer Being that is not collapsible into Being for thought. It must be so collapsible if we are committed to Hegelian absolute idealism.
See also follow-up article โSheer Being and Thoughtโ.
ยฉ Dennis Schulting, 2022.
Ugly as it is, I capitalise Being so as to differentiate it from the participle form of the verb.
Sehr geehrter Dr. Schulting,
I was very impressed by this essay. Maybe I could write a proposal in virtue of your essay. Thanks a lot.
Mit freundlichen Grรผรen
p.s. My profile with Houlgate is a photo which took in Internationale Tagung der Koreanischen Hegel-Gesellschaft 2018.
I guided him from airport to hotel. He was very warmhearted.
- Yun, Hwi Jong -
Hello Dr. Schulting,
I have wanted to reach out to you for a long time, but I have been unable to find contact information for you. Due to your background in philosophy and theology, and particularly your study of the completeness of Kant's table of categories, I would like to send you a courtesy copy of my book, "Christ Condemned: On the Incarnation and the Trinity." It is a full exposition of the critical philosophy and application to the Christian religion, including a proof of the completeness of Kant's table of categories and deduction of the necessity of the fundamentals of Christianity, namely, the Incarnation and the Trinity. If you are interested, I would like to hear any thoughts you may have about my work.
Here is a link to my book: https://www.amazon.com/Christ-Condemned-Incarnation-Trinity/dp/B08SPXXLF6/ref=cm_cr_arp_d_product_top?ie=UTF8
Regards,
Julian Gress